Sunday 22 January 2017

TOLMANS SIGN GESTALT

Tolman'sSign  Learning


The theory of Edward C. Tolman (1886-1959) was called purposive behaviorism in his major systematic work, Purposive behavior in animals and men (1932b). Later he (and others) called it a sign-gestalt theory, a sign-significate theory, or an expectancy theory. These later terms all emphasize the cognitive nature of the theory, which distin-guishes it in certain respects from the stimulus-response theories of Thorndike, Guthrie, Skinner, and Hull. The designation sign learning provides a satisfactory short name, abbreviating sign-gestalt and sign-significate, while calling attention to the cognitive reference within the theory.

Tolman acknowledged the complex affiliations of his system-with Watson's behaviorism, McDougall's hormic psychology, Woodworth's dynamic psychology, and gestalt psychology (in both classical and Lewin's forms). He later recognized a number of parallels between his system and the probabilistic functionalism developed independently by Brunswik (Tolman and Brunswik, 1935). Still later, the influence of psychoanalysis began to be noticeable (1942, 1943). Because of these complex affiliations it is appropriate to consider his system following the treatment of other behaviorisms, and before turning to the nonbehavioristic theories.

Despite some shifts in vocabulary, Tolman held firm to his main tenets during the twenty-seven years between the time his book appeared and his death.


1. His system was a genuine behaviorism, and as such rigidly rejected introspection as a method and "raw feels" as data for psychological sci-


192             THEORIES OF LEARNING

ence. When he made reference to consciousness, to inventive ideation, and the like, he was talking about interpretations of observed behavior. He did not accept "verbal report" as a dodge by which to smuggle con-sciousness in through the back door.

2. The system was a molar, rather than a molecular, behaviorism. An act of behavior has distinctive properties all its own, to be identified and described irrespective of whatever muscular, glandular, or neural proc-esses underlie it. The molecular facts of physics and physiology upon which behavior rests have identifying properties of their own, which are not the properties of behavior as molar. This meant for Tolman an inde-pendence from physiology, a characteristic which he shared with several of the writers whom we have considered.

3. The system was a purposivism, but of a sort to avoid the implica-tions of a teleological metaphysics. It was a purposivism because it recognized that behavior is regulated in accordance with objectively deter-minable ends. It was not mentalistic; purposes are not those of a self-conscious mind. I t is not in agreement with teleological points of view which make effects take precedence over and determine their causes.

The strongest rejection was of American structuralism, because struc-turalism was dependent upon introspection of the most offensive sort, that known as Beschreibung. Watsonian behaviorism was almost as vigor-ously rejected, because it was not only molecular but tended to neglect the problems of goal-seekingbehavior.


THE  SYSTEMATIC POSITION

Behavior as Molar

The descriptive properties of molar behavior are the most general characteristics of behavior which would impress themselves upon an in-telligent onlooker without presuppositions and before any attempt to explain how the behavior comes about.

First, behavior is goal-directed. It is always a getting-toward something, or a getting-away from something. The most significant description of any behavior is what the organism is doing, what it is up to, where it is going. The cat is trying to get out of the box, the carpenter is building a house (or earning a living), the musician is seeking acclaim for his vir-tuosity. The particular movements involved are less descriptive of the molar behavior than is the goal toward which or away from which the movements lead. This feature characterizes molar behavior as purposive.

Second, the behavior makes use of environmental supports as means-objects toward the goal. The world in which behavior goes on is a world




TOLMANsS SIGN LEARNING
193

of paths and tools, obstacles, and by-paths with which the organism has

commerce. The manner in which the organism makes use of  paths and

tools in relation to its goals characterizes molar behavior as cognitive as

well as purposive.

f
Third, there is a selective preference for short or easy means-activities
as against long or difficult ones, called the principle of  least effort.




Fourth, behavior, if it is molar, is docile. That  is, molar behavior is

characterized by teachableness. If it is mechanical and stereotyped, like a

spinal reflex, it belongs at the molecular level. Docility is said to be  a

mark of p u r p o ~ e . ~


Intervening Variables


The complete act of behavior is initiated by environmental stim-

uli  and  physiological states. Certain  processes  intervene,  and  behavior

emerges. Programmatically, this  is  the  formula  which  Hull  took  over

from Tolman. The problem of psychological analysis at the molar level

is to infer the processes which intervene between the initiation of action

in the world of physics and physiology and the resulting observable con-

sequences, again in the world of  physics and physiology. Because all of

the data are rooted in this world, the system remains a behaviorism.


In spite of his methodological behaviorism, Tolman was clearly bent

on making a "psychological"  as against a "physiological"  analysis. The

intervening variables include such processes as cognitions and purposes,

so that, on one side of its ancestry, Tolman's position belongs with the

gestalt psychologists who have been characterized as "centralists,"  rather

than  with  the stimulus-response psychologists characterized as "periph-

eralists."



The  precise  variables entering  into  behavior  determination  did  not

remain fixed in Tolman's later discussions, but his logic of system-making

remained the same. The set of  terms used in his presidential address be-

fore the American Psychological Association in 1937 (Tolman, 1938) may

serve as illustrative.


The background of physiology and physics with which choice-point be-

havior  begins  is  defined  by  environmental  and  individual  difference

variables:



I. Environmental Variables


M
Maintenance schedule


G   Appropriateness of goal object


S   Types and modes of stimuli provided


R
Types of motor response required




1 In this Tolman follows Perry (1918).


194              THEORIES OF LEARNING

S    (OBO)   Cumulative nature and number of  trials2

P       Pattern of preceding and succeeding maze units

11.  Individual DifferenceVariables
H        Heredity
A    Age
T    Previous training

E    Special endocrine, drug or vitamin conditions

It is possible to study the effect of such variables on resulting behavior. The usual learning curve is a plot of the functional relationship under stated conditions. These are the behavioral "facts" about learning. It is the effort to explain the facts which leads to theories.

Tolman's explanation rests on intervening variables. These are in-ferred processes between the independent variables (stimuli, etc.) and the dependent variables (responses, etc.). The preliminary list as pre-sented coordinates one intervening variable with each of the environmen-tal variables.


Intervening  Variable
Environmental  Variable
Demand
correlated with
Maintenance schedule
Appetite
correlated with
Appropriateness of goal object
Differentiation
correlated with
Types and modes of stimuli provided
Motor skill
correlated with
Types of motor response required
Hypotheses
correlated with
Cumulative nature and number of


trials
Biases
correlated with
Pattern of  preceding and succeeding


maze units

Although the intervening variables may sound subjective, in principle each can be given objective definition and measurement through a defin-ing experiment in which everything else is held constant except the cor-relative environmental variable while that one is systematically varied. Demand, for example, may be expected to increase with the number of hours since feeding, but the relationship between food deprivation and demand is not a simple one. It must be studied empirically. The same holds for each of the intervening variables.

Having thus established a basis for inferring the value of the interven-ing variable from the antecedent conditions, the next stage in theory con-struction is to find the equations relating intervening variables to behav-

2 2 (OBO) i s a shoithand formula which means some consequence or summation of previous expeiiences in which one occasion (0) has led through behavior (B) to another occasion (0).The occasions are such features as a choice-point, a goal at the left, and so on.


TOLMAN'SSIGN  LEARNING
195

ioral outcomes, as these intervening variables simultaneously take on different values.

In spite of the clear outline of what a systematic theory ought to be, Tolman nowhere attempted quantitative predictions paralleling those of Hull, so that his conjectures have not in that sense been put to the testes This does not mean that his experiments were unrelated to his theory. There were, in fact, many predictions, but they assert that one path will be preferred to another, that under one set of circumstances the problem will be easier than under another set, and so on. The dimensional analy-sis which completes the function was not provided, and Hull's conscien-tious efforts are instructive in showing how difficult that task proves to be.


SIGN  LEARNING

Sign Learning as an Alternative to Response Learning

Stimulus-response theories, while stated with different degrees of sophistication, imply that the organism is goaded along a path by internal and external stimuli, learning the correct movement sequences so that they are released under appropriate conditions of drive and environmen-tal stimulation. The alternative possibility is that the learner is following signs to a goal, is learning his way about, is following a sort of map-in other words, is learning not movements but meanings. This is the con-tention of Tolman's theory of sign learning. The organism learns sign-significate relations; it learns a behavior route, not a movement pattern. Many learning situations do not permit a dear distinction between these two possibilities. If there is a single path with food at the end and the organism runs faster at each opportunity, there is no way of telling whether his responses are being stamped in by reinforcement or whether he is guided by his immanent purposes and cognitions.

Because both stimulus-response and sign learning so often predict the same behavioral outcome, it is necessary to design special experiments in which it is possible to favor one theory over the other. Three situations give strong support to the sign-learning alternative. These are experi-ments on reward expectancy, on place learning, and on latent learning.

1. Reward expectancy. One of the earliest and most striking observa-tions on reward expectancy was that of Tinklepaugh (1928). I n his ex-periment, food was placed under one of two containers while the monkey was looking but prevented from immediate access to the cans and food. Later the monkey was permitted to choose between the containers and



3 Some starts were made, e.g., Tolman (1939, 1941)

No comments:

Post a Comment